In the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, David Hume sets out to show that all knowledge can be derived from experience. Hume takes a particular look at the experience of cause and effect and our knowledge of the relation between the two. It is in the fourth section of the Enquiry that he presents what one commentator (Peter Millican) describes as Hume's “most celebrated argument” concerning the relation of cause and effects. It is obvious that we experience things of which we call causes and other things which effects, but Hume is interested in how and why one can conclude anything at all from such an experience. Hume answers in part two of the fourth section, that conclusions from an experience of seemingly cause and effect, cannot be founded by reasoning. He therefore takes it as his aim to explain and defend this answer throughout the fourth section and the rest of the text. I will therefore argue in this paper that Hume's argument for his solution functions as a viable defense for his solution.
Prior
to Hume's discussion of cause and effect he makes an important
distinction between two kinds of objects of reason. That is to say a
distinction between the kind of things that one can reason about.
This distinction will aid us in our understanding of Hume's
discussion of cause and effect. One
kind of object of reason is what Hume calls relation of ideas.
By ideas Hume means the less lively and less forcible perceptions of
the mind. Ideas are faint copies of another kind of perception of the
mind known as impressions which are lively perceptions (such as
hearing, seeing, feeling) and are forced upon our minds. Relation of
ideas Hume means, “every
affirmation, which is either intuitively or demonstratively
certain”(4.1) Things that are intuitively certain are things that
are known through a direct intellectual grasp, such as our knowledge
that 2+2=4. Things that are demonstratively certain are things which
can be proven by a sequence of intuitive steps, such as a proof of
Pythagoras’s Theorem (that the square of the hypotenuse of a
triangle is equal to the square of its two other sides). Relation of
ideas are thus objects of reasons which can be known a priori. By a
priori I do not mean to imply that there is any innate knowledge in
people (recall
that ideas are derive from impressions which are derived from
experience),
but that only that it can be justified without experience.
The second kind of
objects of reason Hume calls matters of fact. Matters of fact are in
contrast, a posteriori, that is they can only be learned through
experience. They concern ideas in relation to the actual world. For
example, it is a matter of fact that words are appearing on the
screen of my computer after I press buttons on my keyboard. And it is
not a contradiction to suppose that a matter of fact such as this
could be otherwise. For it could be the case that I press the buttons
on my keyboard and birds start to fly out my computer screen. For
this reason Hume thinks that “every matter of fact is still
possible” (4.2) since every outcome which we conceive by the mind
would have the same “facility and distinctness” (4.2). Therefore,
matters of fact cannot be demonstratively or intuitively certain.
Now we have
sufficient understanding of Hume's distinction of objects of reason
to proceed to unravel his enquiry of cause and effect. Hume decides
to investigate a little deeper into the nature of the evidence that
gives us an assurance of matters of fact. Matters of fact he states
are found on relations of cause and effects. Recall, I found that it
is a matter of fact that words appear on my computer screen after I
pressed keys on my keyboard. And still as I continue to type this
paper I am making an on-going inference that there is a connexion
between my pressing the keys and words appearing on the screen. But
on grounds is this inference made? Hume answers that the connexion
between cause and effect is not intuitive and there is a required
medium (grounds) from which to make the inference. As this is as
Hume says a “new” (4.17) question we should not trust our own
“penetration” (4.17) of the question and instead lay out all the
different kinds of reasonings and show that none of them make a
viable medium for inferences of cause and effect.
Hume divides all
reasoning into two kinds, demonstrative reasoning and moral
reasoning. Demonstrative reasoning is the reasoning concerning
relation of ideas. Arguments from this kind of reasoning involve
intuitive steps such as, if you recall, my earlier example of
Pythagoras’s theorem. Moral reasoning concerns matters of fact and
involves uncertain inductive steps. I am using moral reasoning to
infer at this moment that words will continue to appear on my screen
after I press the keys because that has been the case several times
in the past. Therefore, if Hume is to show that our conclusions from
experience of cause and effect cannot be derived from reason he will
have to show that that these kinds of reasoning are not plausible
mediums from which to infer the connexion between cause and effect.
Hume first refutes
the possibility that the grounds for the inference of cause and
effect can be founded on demonstrative reasoning. Demonstrative
reasoning if you recall are always certain. That is, a denial of it
would imply a contradiction. 2+2=4 can be not be conceived to be any
other way or else it would be a contradiction. But as Hume points
out, “it implies no contradiction that the course of nature may
change” (4.18). For there is no contradiction in supposing that
birds may fly out of computer screen after I press on the keys. Such
conceptions would seem to oppose the nature of demonstrative
reasoning. Another much simpler refutation to this kind of reasoning
is that demonstrative reasoning requires no experience, but we need
experience in order to infer an effects from its cause. For a person
that has never seen a gun could not infer without experience that a
bullet will be fired after the trigger is pulled.
Hume then continues
to investigate whether moral reasoning could be a plausible medium
for the inference. We have said that matters of fact are founded on
the relations of cause and effects, and that we know that relation
from experience. In our ending conclusion we want to be able to say
that the future will resemble the past. But in moral reasoning this
means, the future will resemble the past, because future has always
resemble the past. But this doesn't tell us why the future must still
resemble the past. The evidence itself supposes the conclusion which
generates a circular argument.
It must follow then
that our conclusions from experiences of cause and effects (namely
that there is a connexion between the two) cannot be founded on
reason. This negative argument (one that derives it conclusion
through the negation of the other options) is one that is not only
plausible but also perfectly viable if we are to accept Hume's
empiricist philosophy. For in order to refute Hume, one would either
have to show how relation of ideas and matters of fact do not cover
the all objects of reasoning, or prove that there is an object-less
reasoning which both exists and is viable solution for making
inferences of cause and effect. Otherwise we must accept as Hume does
in the fifth section of the Enquiry
that we only draw conclusions of cause and effect out of a habit of
seeing the events constantly conjoined.
0 comments :
Post a Comment